Picking out the key ideas of John Dewey’s philosophy is a challenge given that his work fills thirty-seven volumes that he spent over seventy years writing on various topics. Thus, this list could have gone many ways. This article will focus on five: his theory of inquiry, instrumentalism, political philosophy, moral philosophy, and philosophy on education. He was mainly regarded for his philosophy and his pedagogy, but being labeled as a philosopher and an educator meant he garnered two very different audiences. He was controversial from his start, and he continues to spark criticism, but there is no negating that he was one of the most important thinkers to emerge in the United States in the first half of the twentieth century.
Dewey’s Theory of Inquiry
Common to the other pragmatists, inquiry was fundamentally central in Dewey’s philosophy; this is the core of any theories we create about knowledge and what he would call “warranted assertions” to replace the term “truth.” The role of inquiry is to resolve problems and/or doubts. This is how it proceeds: a problem(s) or doubt(s) arises, for which we have theories, but which might be revised as we gain new insights via the scientific methodology working through the problem or doubt. Our aim in this process is the “warranted assertibility” of the resolution of that problem or doubt in a new or newly refined settled belief. There is also an important connection to biology here for Dewey: the motivation behind this process is to achieve a state of stability and harmony. But as is commonly misconstrued about pragmatism, this is not an anything-goes position as another important part of our motivation is our desire not just to solve problems and doubts, but to get things right, or at least try to. Still, what we should expect to obtain is security rather than certainty, at least most of the time. We want reliable solutions that follow the evidence; the solutions satisfy the needs of not just the inquirer, but the inquirer’s environment as well. And like some, but not all, others labeled “pragmatists,” there is no separation between subject and object; we are always inquirers inextricably tied to our environments.
Instrumentalism
No thinker labeled “pragmatist” took on that term whole-heartedly; none of them were quite sure that this was the best word to describe their methods, all of which had relevant differences as well. In the case of Dewey, when applying that term, perhaps it is best to do so by describing his work as “pragmatic” in nature rather than as “pragmatism.” However, Dewey generally referred to his method as “instrumentalism.” His is a process philosophy; our ideas and beliefs are instruments for achieving some end. Meaning, we live in a world that makes demands on us, and we must respond. When presented with doubts and problems, we must think about how to resolve them within the context of our personal, social, and environmental lives. Inquiry involves confusion and resolution. Inquiry is forward-looking because the eventual warranted assertions we may arrive at require a process of verification in the future.
As a “process philosophy,” it never ends. We are constantly confronting doubts and problems that need resolving. Our theories need to be frequently adjusted when, as instruments, they no longer work as they once did. When we have an inquiry, it presupposes that there is an answer and that we can go out and verify it. Thus, an inquiry warrants an assertion, presumably, that assertion is warranted by inquiry, which then resolves the problematic situation that gave rise to that inquiry—this is always inextricably interconnected in this way in Dewey’s philosophy.
Political Philosophy
For Dewey, everything is bound up with his theory of inquiry; this is where everything starts, including politics. As we have seen, his theory of inquiry proceeds as follows: a practical problem(s) or doubt(s) arises, for which we have theories, but which might be revised as we gain new insights via the scientific methodology working through the problem or doubt as it plays out broadly in society. Democracy is such a process by definition; it is a collaborative effort in this endeavor. This is tied to his moral philosophy in that democracy is the community of inquirers working to achieve a communal society that is harmonious and stable. The needs of all those within the community are deliberated upon to determine how to achieve the most ideal situation for all involved. Thus, again, problems and doubts, whether about politics or ethics, are resolved, ideally, in this process of inquiry. Democracy is critical in this process because the beliefs we hold should stand up to all experiences, not just our own; we must consider others because we always live with others. Democracy, then, is such a collective process.
Dewey, as with several other pragmatists, emphasizes meliorism, or the position essentially of warranted assertion; we may not acquire absolute certainty in our beliefs, but we can hopefully acquire reasonable stability and harmony--all of which can lead to a better life, broadly speaking.
Moral Philosophy
Dewey’s moral philosophy is arguably more developed than any other labeled pragmatist—perhaps in part because of his long life (he outlived Willam James and Charles Sanders Peirce, for example, by about four decades). Ethics is tied to his theory of inquiry: the same applies to problems and doubts of an ethical nature. Thus, through deliberation in our process of inquiry, we construct meaning, with the aim of being better selves both personally and especially socially given we all live in societies. Dewey focuses on progress and growth rather than ends, which is also what drew many critics since it does not provide any absolute moral certainties, but it does align more with pragmatist thought.
As inquiry is meant to satisfy the needs of the inquirer and his or her environment, so too does moral judgment. A moral problem(s) or doubt(s) arises, for which we have theories, but which might be revised as we gain new insights via the scientific methodology working through the moral problem or doubt. We think, we reflect, we get more information, we experiment directly or just in the mind, we deliberate over our needs and those of the environment, and we consider if adjustments need to be made—all, again, intending to be better human beings living in human societies. This process of inquiry is so important because it unveils the value we place on things and needs; until we engage in this process, we do not know what we value or what is valuable broadly.
Philosophy on Education
As we are problem-solving instruments ourselves, as well as the theories we create, life is essentially experimental. The same applies to education; it must be flexible to the ever-changing world we find ourselves in. And as shared with other pragmatists as a general aim, the goal is to improve our lives—directly and practically. Nothing, argued Dewey, is more effective in this endeavor than education.
As many other important thinkers have argued, Dewey believes we are creatures of habits, and schools exist primarily to cultivate the right habits. Theories on pedagogy require flexibility for adapting to changes that lead to new or altered needs. The best kind of educator is someone like Socrates; an individual who teaches his or her students to think critically, rationally, and logically. It should focus on cultivating students’ creativity. It is not a person who forces rote memorization upon their students. Inquiry should be pursued individually, not forced upon others. However, the role of the other is critical as well; in connection with his emphasis on democracy, an inquiry must involve taking into consideration as many other perspectives as possible; the good of the whole depends on the good of its parts. We live in a society, so our particular habits as individuals can overlap with those of our community. The self is a social self that takes on socially conditioned habits for Dewey. Those habits create meaning in the world by guiding our actions and producing practical consequences. It is through learning that we create those habits, presented via education. Considering Dewey’s stress on experiment, it was apt that some called the private elementary school he founded as an “educational laboratory.” Taking a Darwinian approach, Dewey considered the educator and the student as both ever evolving toward continued success in being better in their roles; the best inquiries will arise to be resolved toward progress. Education is always met with more education.
Dewey had much to say about epistemology, political philosophy, moral philosophy, aesthetics, naturalism, the philosophy of mind, and the philosophy of education, to name some of his areas of concentration. While some charge that he left some topics unclear or unfinished, despite the plethora of work he produced, this nonetheless is consistent with pragmatism; with the task of their philosophy being to produce a method that aims to make life better, but that is an unceasing process. Thus, one might surmise that the meaning of life for this kind of pragmatist is to continually make more meaning, and this is why education is of fundamental importance; philosophy is an inquiry into education, primarily.